Results for 'Terence John Pell'

991 found
Order:
  1. The Source of Normativity.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2023 - Mind 132 (527):706-729.
    This paper seeks to clarify one of the deepest questions about the source or ground of normativity, while also presenting an essence-based approach to answering it. We call it the ‘Arché Question.’ Though all metanormative theories must address this question, very few realists have explicitly grappled with the challenge it poses; those who have appear to deny any need to give an answer. After critically discussing extant realist responses, this paper outlines an essence-based approach to answering the Arché Question that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  87
    Philosophical Methodology: From Data to Theory.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2022 - Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau.
    Philosophical Methodology offers an up-to-date assessment of different methods of doing philosophy, and develops a novel account of the structure and goals of inquiry. It allows philosophers and students of philosophy to better understand their topics, and shows how philosophy can continue to make progress in answering its central questions.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3. The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oup Usa. pp. 520--533.
  4.  63
    Comments on Sterba’s “The Michigan Cases and Furthering the Justification of Affirmative Action”.Terence J. Pell - 2004 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (1):35-38.
    In my comments on Prof. Sterba’s paper, I argue that evidence about the educational value of racial preferences reveals not that these policies produce good educational outcomes, but that schools use racial preferences regardless of whether they produce desirable outcomes. I further argue that in the absence of objective evidence about the value of racial preferences, proponents of these policies tend to rely on personal anecdotes. Often, these anecdotes reveal complex institutional and personal motives having little to do with the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  44
    Racial preferences and formal equality.Terence J. Pell - 2003 - Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (2):309–325.
  6.  62
    The Nature of Claims About Race and the Debate Over Racial Preferences.Terence J. Pell - 2004 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (1):13-26.
    In this paper, I argue that assertions about the value of diversity rely on contradictory and incommensurable claims. As a result, institutions like the Supreme Court find it impossible to articulate an impartial standard for the appropriate use of race in college admissions. I argue that in the absence of such a standard, institutions inevitably fall back on engineering proportional racial outcomes, a method of college admissions that disproportionately harms minority students.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  30
    What's the big deal about racial preferences?Terence J. Pell - 2003 - Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (2):326–329.
  8. Trusting Moral Intuitions.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2019 - Noûs (4):956-984.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  96
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1996 - MIT Press.
    In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, Horgan and Tienson articulate and defend a new view of cognition.
  10.  87
    Pricean reflection.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2022 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31 (4):744-761.
    We offer a reconstruction of Richard Price’s intuition-based epistemology of normative essences, highlighting its key elements and showing how it differs from the approaches taken by other intuitionists such as Thomas Reid and G. E. Moore, as well as sentimentalists such as Francis Hutcheson and David Hume. While our analysis aims to shed light on Price’s moral epistemology, it also seeks to contribute to contemporary debates about the epistemology of essence, advancing a general intuition-based theory. These two goals are related, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  72
    Socially conscious moral intuitionism.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2023 - Noûs 57 (4):986-994.
    In “Trusting Moral Intuitions” we argued that moral intuitions are trustworthy due to their being the outputs of a cognitive practice, with social elements, in good working order. Backes, Eklund, and Michelson present several criticisms of our defense of a socially conscious moral intuitionism. We respond to these criticisms, defending our claim that social factors enhance the epistemic credentials of moral intuitions, answering worries pertaining to the reliability of the moral intuition practice, and addressing concerns about both the individuation of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Method in the Service of Progress.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2019 - Analytic Philosophy 60 (3):179-205.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  84
    Representations without Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-174.
  14. The Projectability Challenge to Moral Naturalism.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Andrew Reisner - 2020 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 17 (5):471-498.
    The Projectability Challenge states that a metaethical view must explain how ordinary agents can, on the basis of moral experience and reflection, accurately and justifiably apply moral concepts to novel situations. In this paper, we argue for two primary claims. First, paradigm nonnaturalism can satisfactorily answer the projectability challenge. Second, it is unclear whether there is a version of moral naturalism that can satisfactorily answer the challenge. The conclusion we draw is that there is an important respect in which nonnaturalism (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15. The First Critique Reflections on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.John James Macintosh & Terence Penelhum - 1969 - Wadsworth.
  16. Jesus on the Mountain: A Study in Matthean Theology.Terence L. Donaldson, Stephen Farris & John S. Pobee - 1985
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Phenomenal intentionality and the brain in a vat.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  18. Internal-World Skepticism and the Self-Presentational Nature of Phenomenal Consciousness.Terence Horgan, John Tienson & Graham George - 2006 - In Kriegel Uriah & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-representational Approaches to Consciousness. Bradford.
  19.  24
    Representations without Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-174.
  20. The phenomenology of first-person agency.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2003 - In Sven Walter & Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation. Imprint Academic. pp. 323.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  21.  52
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.) - 1991 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    "A third of the papers in this volume originated at the 1987 Spindel Conference ... at Memphis State University"--Pref.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  22. Deconstructing new wave materialism.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2001 - In Carl Gillett & Barry M. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press. pp. 307--318.
    In the first post World War II identity theories (e.g., Place 1956, Smart 1962), mind brain identities were held to be contingent. However, in work beginning in the late 1960's, Saul Kripke (1971, 1980) convinced the philosophical community that true identity statements involving names and natural kind terms are necessarily true and furthermore, that many such necessary identities can only be known a posteriori. Kripke also offered an explanation of the a posteriori nature of ordinary theoretical identities such as that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  23. Methods, goals, and data in moral theorizing.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2018 - In Aaron Zimmerman, Karen Jones & Mark Timmons (eds.), Routledge Handbook on Moral Epistemology. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Methods, goals, and data in moral theorizing.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2018 - In Aaron Zimmerman, Karen Jones & Mark Timmons (eds.), Routledge Handbook on Moral Epistemology. Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  53
    Soft laws.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1990 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1):256-279.
  26. A nonclassical framework for cognitive science.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1994 - Synthese 101 (3):305-45.
    David Marr provided a useful framework for theorizing about cognition within classical, AI-style cognitive science, in terms of three levels of description: the levels of (i) cognitive function, (ii) algorithm and (iii) physical implementation. We generalize this framework: (i) cognitive state transitions, (ii) mathematical/functional design and (iii) physical implementation or realization. Specifying the middle, design level to be the theory of dynamical systems yields a nonclassical, alternative framework that suits (but is not committed to) connectionism. We consider how a brain's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  27. Consciousness and intentionality.George Graham, Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2007 - In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Blackwell. pp. 468--484.
  28.  26
    Review symposia.Terence McMullen, John Maze, Joel Michell & Brian Kennedy - 1996 - Metascience 5 (2):6-20.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Cognitive systems as dynamic systems.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1992 - Topoi 11 (1):27-43.
  30.  67
    Representation without rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-74.
  31.  31
    Levels of Description in Nonclassical Cognitive Science.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 34:159-188.
    David Marr provided an influential account of levels of description in classical cognitive science. In this paper we contrast Marr'ent with some alternatives that are suggested by the recent emergence of connectionism. Marr's account is interesting and important both because of the levels of description it distinguishes, and because of the way his presentation reflects some of the most basic, foundational, assumptions of classical AI-style cognitive science. Thus, by focusing on levels of description, one can sharpen foundational differences between classicism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  78
    Connectionism and the commitments of folk psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:127-52.
  33.  43
    Settling into a new paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 26 (S1):97-113.
  34.  9
    Low temperature dislocation mechanisms in ordered and disordered Cu3Au.Terence G. Langdon & John E. Dorn - 1968 - Philosophical Magazine 17 (149):999-1015.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  19
    Settling into a new paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 26 (S1):241--260.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  36.  2
    Settling Into a New Paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):97-113.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Structured representations in connectionist systems?Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1991 - In S. Davis (ed.), Connectionism: Theorye and Practice. Oxford University Press.
  38. Internal-world skepticism and mental self-presentation.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2006 - In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. MIT Press. pp. 41-61.
  39.  17
    Dative questions: A study in the relation of acceptability to grammaticality of an english sentence type.D. Terence Langendoen, Nancy Kalish-Landon & John Dore - 1973 - Cognition 2 (4):451-478.
  40. Authors' replies.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1999 - Acta Analytica 144:275-287.
  41. Cognition needs syntax but not rules.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2006 - In Robert J. Stainton (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 147--158.
    Human cognition is rich, varied, and complex. In this Chapter we argue that because of the richness of human cognition (and human mental life generally), there must be a syntax of cognitive states, but because of this very richness, cognitive processes cannot be describable by exceptionless rules. The argument for syntax, in Section 1, has to do with being able to get around in any number of possible environments in a complex world. Since nature did not know where in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Spindel Conference 1987 Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1988 - Dept. Of Philosophy, Memphis State University.
  43.  35
    Representations don't need rules: Reply to James Garson.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (1):1-24.
  44.  4
    Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2017 - In William Bechtel & George Graham (eds.), A Companion to Cognitive Science. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 660–670.
    Contemporary cognitive science has two principal branches: the classical computational approach (sometimes called classicism) and connectionism. Rules are fundamental to theorizing about the basic units of processing in both classicism and connectionism. But we will be concerned primarily with rules that apply to representations and that determine transitions from one cognitive/representational state to the next. Such rules are fundamental to classicism, since, according to classicism, cognitive processes simply are rule‐governed cognitive state transitions. Rules that apply to representations are not a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  51
    Levels of description in nonclassical cognitive science.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1992 - Philosophy 34:159-188.
    David Marr provided an influential account of levels of description in classical cognitive science. In this paper we contrast Marr'ent with some alternatives that are suggested by the recent emergence of connectionism. Marr's account is interesting and important both because of the levels of description it distinguishes, and because of the way his presentation reflects some of the most basic, foundational, assumptions of classical AI-style cognitive science . Thus, by focusing on levels of description, one can sharpen foundational differences between (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  26
    Pr cis of connectionism and the philosophy of psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (3):337 – 356.
    Connectionism was explicitly put forward as an alternative to classical cognitive science. The questions arise: how exactly does connectionism differ from classical cognitive science, and how is it potentially better? The classical “rules and representations” conception of cognition is that cognitive transitions are determined by exceptionless rules that apply to the syntactic structure of symbols. Many philosophers have seen connectionism as a basis for denying structured symbols. We, on the other hand, argue that cognition is too rich and flexible to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  56
    Resisting the tyranny of terminology: The general dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):643-643.
    What van Gelder calls the dynamical hypothesis is only a special case of what we here dub the general dynamical hypothesis. His terminology makes it easy to overlook important alternative dynamical approaches in cognitive science. Connectionist models typically conform to the general dynamical hypothesis, but not to van Gelder's.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  28
    Letters to the Editor.Terence Irwin, John Rowehl, Leonard D. Katz, David A. Hoekema & Mitchell Aboulafia - 1992 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66 (1):33 - 35.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind.George Graham, Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2007 - In Brian P. McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 512--537.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  21
    Symposium: Is Analysis a Useful Method in Philosophy?Max Black, John Terence Wisdom & Maurice Cornforth - 1934 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 13 (1):53 - 118.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 991